Exploring the Ethics of Forgiveness Through Derrida and Jankélévitch
The notion of forgiveness fosters contention and disagreement on many aspects, yet
remains a necessary aspect of the harmonization and collaboration of societies as they
come to terms with the often violent histories that exist. Despite extensive literature
on the many issues involved, there is still little agreement found in philosophical
literature on what forgiving actually entails (Govier 1999). A particularly
controversial aspect of the concept of forgiveness is whether forgiveness of the
unforgivable is possible – and whether it is ethical. Vladimir Jankélévitch’s article
Should we Pardon Them? published in 1996, outlines his belief that crimes against
humanity, such as the Holocaust, are unforgivable. Jacques Derrida has subsequently
submitted his criticism of Jankélévitch, radically proposing that, “forgiveness forgives
only the unforgivable” (2001, p 32), and pure forgiveness therefore constitutes an
element of impossibility. The continuing debate and criticisms of both philosophers
reveals the difficulty in establishing a unified theory of forgiveness and its limits;
however, generally, forgiveness can be considered supererogatory, a relatively
recently defined concept which suggests that although the act is considered morally
good, it is not obligatory (Heyd 2015). Simplistically, forgiveness can be defined as
“the act of giving up a feeling, such as resentment, or a claim to requital or
compensation” (Hughes 2015). Further elements often considered necessary for the
act of forgiveness include repentance by the perpetrator, reconciliation of a
relationship between two individuals, and the relinquishing of feelings of revenge.
However, questions involving who can forgive, what they can forgive, and when and
how they can forgive highlights the difficulty of establishing a coherent definition of
forgiveness. These problems are unpacked further below.
Defining Forgiveness
Forgiveness may involve the relatively uncontroversial concept of relinquishing
feelings of revenge and resentment towards the perpetrator, and, the more
controversial concept that there is a reconciliation of a relationship between the
perpetrator and the victim (Jeffery 2008). South African Archbishop Desmond Tutu
wrote that forgiveness involves “waiving one’s right to revenge” and “abandoning
your right to pay back the perpetrator in his own coin” (Tutu quoted in Jeffery 2008).
Furthermore, Hannah Arendt (1958) maintains that “forgiveness is the exact opposite
of vengeance”, as a central aim of forgiveness is to end a period of suffering for the
victim by letting go of feelings such as vengeance and resentment in order to
constructively move on in their lives; seeking revenge only serves to perpetuate the
harm. True forgiveness also demands that the victim surrender all forms of negative
emotions such as resentment towards the perpetrator (Minkkinen 2007). While this
might not seem achievable in reality, it certainly seems the goal of many who forgive
for the purpose of moving on. The link between forgiveness and resentment was
initially established by Bishop Joseph Butler, who suggested that forgiveness requires
relinquishing feelings of resentment towards the wrong-doer (Griswold 2011). Giving
up negative emotions such as revenge and resentment relieves both the victim and the
wrong-doer, allowing both to move past the event. This is not always necessary, as
binding the victim to the perpetrator’s own repentance seems unjust; however,
political and justice scenarios often seem to require an admission of guilt and
repentance as evidence that the perpetrator should be forgiven. Of course, this is only
an aspect of the far wider picture.
Finally, it has been argued that the process of forgiveness is complete when there is a
reestablishment of a positive relationship between the victim and the perpetrator. It
has been established that there are two possible forms of forgiveness: unconditional
and conditional (Lang 1994). While unconditional forgiveness does not demand a
response from the perpetrator, conditional forgiveness binds the forgiveness offered
by the victim with a form of repentance and remorse from the perpetrator (Govier
1999). Conditional forgiveness is a particularly controversial form, with philosophers
such as Derrida suggesting that it is not forgiveness at all, but a kind of reconciliation.
Garrard (2002) suggests that forgiveness requires “the adoption of a particular attitude
towards the perpetrator, an attitude which can be broadly described as wishing him
well” (Garrard 2002, p 155). Therefore, conditional forgiveness requires a mutual
reconciliation of a relationship. Unconditional forgiveness, however, does not require
a mutual re-establishment of relationship (Lang 1994, p 105). Arguments in favour of
unconditional forgiveness stem from the belief that it is unfair to the victim to require
that they cannot forgive until the perpetrator has repented for their actions; it can be
said that this grants even more power to the actions of the perpetrator over the victim
(Garrard and MacNaughton 2003). Perhaps the most convincing argument is that both
conditional and unconditional forgiveness are possible; however, neither are
necessary (Hughes 2014). If the perpetrator offers an apology or other form of
repentance, it might be easier for the victim to consider forgiveness (Tutu in Jeffery
2008); however, it is the right of the victim to decide when, if ever, they wish to
forgive.
There is great debate over who can offer forgiveness. While some writers maintain
that only the true victims can forgive the perpetrator (Jankélévitch 1996), others argue
that forgiveness can be offered by third parties, including political bodies (Hughes
2014). It seems more convincing to argue that only the victim can offer forgiveness,
where they forgive the harm that the perpetrator has caused them. Jankélévitch
supports this when he questions, “Everyone is free to pardon the offences that he has
personally suffered if he chooses… [but] what qualifies the survivors to pardon in the
place of the victims…?” (Jankelevich 1996, p 496). Jankelevich argues that certain
acts are so heinous that no one has the moral right to forgive them, and these acts
must remain unforgivable in perpetuity.
Jankélévitch and the Unforgivable
In his article Should we Pardon Them?, Jankélévitch writes that there are some
crimes, those “against the human essence” (Jankélévitch 1996, p 555), which are
unforgivable. The Holocaust is an example of such a crime, as it “is the product of
pure wickedness, of ontological wickedness, of the most diabolical and gratuitous
wickedness” (original emphasis Jankélévitch 1996, p 556). Time cannot provide
comfort for these crimes, but only increases the pain suffered by the public.
Jankélévitch seems to advocate for a conditional sense of forgiveness, where it is
possible to forgive those who had repented; however, where there has been a crime
against humanity, he maintains that it cannot be ethically possible to forgive those
involved. Those he considers to have the most power to forgive are those who were
tortured and murdered, and therefore are no longer alive to offer their forgiveness
(1996, p 496). Furthermore, the Holocaust was, according to Jankélévitch, not a
standard act of war or regular atrocity; it was a “work of hatred” (Jankélévitch 1996, p
561), and therefore justifies being considered unforgivable. Jankélévitch also
harbours a fear that forgiving those who persecuted the Jews would also entail
forgetting: “If we ceased to think of them we would complete their extermination, and
they would be definitively annihilated” (1996, p 571). Similar to Jankélévitch, Simon
Wiesenthal recounts in his book The Sunflower: On the Possibility and Limits of
Forgiveness that while he was imprisoned by the Nazis during 1941 to 1945, he was
brought before a dying Nazi soldier who wished to repent and seek the forgiveness of
a Jew; however, Wiesenthal left the dying man without saying a word (Wiesenthal
1998). It seems that for Wiesenthal and Jankélévitch, there is no separation of the evil
deed from the person who committed it, but the act was so evil that the person became
inseparable from it, which Govier writes may justify judging an individual as
absolutely unforgivable (1999, p 67). These expressions of an inability to offer
forgiveness for those who have committed the most heinous crimes are
understandable; however, it still remains questionable whether these crimes should be
considered unforgivable, and whether or not this means that they cannot, ever, be
forgiven.
Reflecting on Jankélévitch’s writings in the modern context, it is clear that the
concept of forgiveness in the face of acts that seem unforgivable is still pertinent. In
2008, then Prime Minister Kevin Rudd offered an apology to the Indigenous
Australian ‘Stolen Generation’ on behalf of the Australian government, evidence of
the society’s need to address the persistent negative emotions and suffering that
remain from this period of history. More recently, the bombings of the Twin Towers
on September 11 th 2011, and the current acts of terrorism and violence being
committed in the name of the Islamic State of Iraq and Syria (ISIS), indicate that
horrific acts are still committed around the world, leaving individuals and whole
communities to comprehend and respond. While many experience emotions of
violence and the desire for revenge, others grasp for ways to relinquish these negative
emotions and forgive. According to Jankélévitch’s theory, no forgiveness can be
offered for these crimes as those who truly suffered are dead, and to forgive would
mean to forget. In contrast, it can be argued that the ramifications of these historic
acts of violence still cause pain and suffering today, directly and indirectly, and gives
rise to the question why these subsequent victims can’t also consider offering
forgiveness.
Derrida’s Paradox of Forgiveness
Derrida’s On Forgiveness offers a criticism of Jankélévitch’s approach to the
unforgivable, formulating instead the issue of forgiveness as a paradox. According to
Derrida, “forgiveness forgives only the unforgivable” (2001, p 32). This stems from
his argument that if a victim is prepared to forgive an act that she considers
forgivable, “the very idea of forgiveness would disappear” (Derrida 2001, p 32).
Derrida writes that there is a distinction between conditional forgiveness, as a reaction
to “repentance, to the transformation of the sinner who then explicitly asks
forgiveness” (2001, p 35) and unconditional forgiveness, that which he considers,
“gracious, infinite, aneconomic… granted to the guilty as guilty” (original emphasis,
Derrida 2001, p 34). Therefore, pure forgiveness, according to Derrida, can be found
only in an ethics beyond ethics, in a mad and impossible situation beyond human
possibility. He refuses the arguments put forward by Jankélévitch and Arendt who
maintain the importance of a forgiveness within the realm of human possibility and
which has a correlation to punishment (Derrida 2001, p 37). Instead, while the
concept of conditional forgiveness is often invoked in social and political situations,
this is not, according to Derrida, a pure form of forgiveness, but closer to an imperfect
form of reconciliation or amnesty (Wyschogrod 2006). Pure forgiveness must engage
the radical disjunction of self and other, but as soon as a third party taints this
engagement, it becomes impure (Derrida 2001, p 42). Conditional forgiveness
breaches this relationship of self and other by demanding that the victim has some
understanding of the reasons and motivations behind the acts of the perpetrator before
they offer forgiveness (Reynolds 2015). Despite the unconditional and the conditional
being “absolutely heterogeneous”, these poles must be “irreconcilable but
indissociable”, and therefore cannot exist without the other (Derrida 2001, p 45). Pure
forgiveness, according to Derrida, is extraordinary and cannot be reduced to the
normative (2001, p 32). This paradox, therefore, reveals that there are unforgivable
acts, and these acts are precisely those that have the ability to be forgiven. Those acts
that are forgivable do not require discussion, as they are not the most serious of
crimes. Individuals can attempt to forgive the unforgivable; however, they will most
likely offer an impure version of conditional forgiveness (Wyschogrod 2006), more
similar to amnesty and reconciliation, rather than the pure and extraordinary
unconditional forgiveness as formulated by Derrida.
The Unforgivable: A Practical Approach
While Derrida and Jankélévitch provide convincing arguments in favour of the ability
to judge some acts as absolutely unforgivable, one could argue that a theory of
supererogatory forgiveness seems more realistic. To regard an individual or act as
unforgivable would be to demand that no one, under any circumstances, would be
able to forgive that person or act (Norlock and Rumsey 2009, p 112). As mentioned
earlier, Jankélévitch seems to argue that where unforgivable deeds have been
committed, it is impossible to separate the perpetrator from their act, and it is the
individual as well as the act that is unforgivable. This seems unjust on a number of
levels. First, with regard to the perpetrator, this would involve rejecting
unconditionally their moral autonomy and ability to change, “the very foundation of
human worth and dignity” (Govier 1999, p 71). Furthermore, with regard to the
victim, judging an act or individual as absolutely unforgivable seems to apply a
greater burden to the victim, restricting unconditional forgiveness (Govier 1999, p
71). For many, “forgiveness is the best or the only path to personal as well as social
healing and reconciliation” (Brudholm and Rosoux 2009, p 34), and denying a victim
of this ability will effectively limit them to harbouring their burden indefinitely. It
might therefore be beneficial to retain a distance between the individual and the act
itself; however, this can be difficult, especially where the perpetrator offers no signs
of repentance or regret.
Furthermore, Derrida’s paradox of forgiveness does not necessarily suggest that the
person committing the unforgivable act cannot be forgiven; ultimately, the acts are
unforgivable due to their fundamentally horrific nature. If the victim is able to
separate this act from the individual, they are able to approach the perpetrator as a
flawed human being, rather than an unforgivable one, and in this case, forgiveness can
be offered. Even where an individual is trying to forgive the unforgivable act, or is
unable to separate the act from the individual, Derrida suggests that forgiveness “can
only be possible when doing the impossible” (2001 p 33). Therefore, while the quality
of forgiveness is outside the realm of regular ethics, this does not mean it is
impossible or unachievable.
Conclusion
The concept of forgiveness in ethics is widely debated and there is very little
consensus on the many aspects of the issue. While Jankélévitch maintains that those
acts that offend the inherent humanity of the victim are so heinous as to be judged as
unforgivable, Derrida responds by radically proposing that it is in fact only those acts
that are unforgivable that justify forgiveness. When faced with the horrific crimes still
occurring around the world today, many are turning to forgiveness to recover and
move on. Therefore, while it would seem that many crimes against humanity are
considered unforgivable, it is important for humans to have the ability to forgive these
crimes. Forgiveness benefits both the victims of the crime, if they offer it, and the
perpetrator, if they are willing to accept it. Furthermore, while clearly direct victims
of the crime have the strongest and perhaps most ‘pure’ form of forgiveness, often
crimes of the nature to be considered unforgivable are those whose horror reach far
across cultures and societies. The ramifications of these acts affect individuals who
were perhaps not directly related to the act, but suffer nonetheless. Therefore, while
Jankélévitch’s arguments on the unforgivable nature of acts against humanity are
understandable, the ability or permission to forgive these acts is necessary for many to
relinquish the negative emotions that burden them. Instead, Derrida’s paradox
highlights the incomprehensible, yet utterly fundamental role forgiveness plays in
restoring harmony and cohesion between people and their pasts.
By Grace Burgess-Limerick
Bachelor of Laws
Bachelor of Arts, Majoring in Philosophy
Bibliography
Arendt, H 1958, ‘On Forgiveness’, The Human Condition, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Brudholm, T and Rosoux, V 2009, ‘The Unforgiving: Reflections on the Resistance to Forgiveness after Atrocity’, Law and Contemporary Problems, vol 72, no 2, pp 33-49.
Derrida, J 2001, ‘On Forgiveness’, in Simon Critchley and Richard Kearney (ed.), On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness, Routledge, London, pp 27-60.
Jeffery, R 2008, ‘To Forgive the Unforgivable?’, in Renee Jeffery (ed.), Confronting Evil in International Relations, Palgrave Macmillan, New York.
Lang, B 1994, ‘Forgiveness’, American Philosophical Quarterly, vol 31, no 2, pp 105-17.
Garrard, E 2002, ‘Forgiveness and the Holocaust’, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, vol 5, no 2, pp 147-65.
Govier, T 1999, ‘Forgiveness and the Unforgivable’, American Philosophical Quarterly, vol 36, no 1, pp 59-75.
Griswold, C 2015, ‘On Forgiveness’, Practical Ethics, web blog post, 17 January 2011, viewed 8 June 2015, <http://blog.practicalethics.ox.ac.uk/2011/01/on-forgiveness/>
Heyd, D 2015, ‘Supererogation’, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, viewed 10 July 2016, < http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/supererogation/>
Hughes, P 2015, ‘Forgiveness’, Stanford Encyclodpedia of Philosophy, viewed 10 June 2015, <http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/forgiveness/>.
Jankélévitch, V 1996, ‘Should We Pardon Them?’, Critical Inquiry, vol 22, no 31, pp 552-72.
Reynolds, J 2015, ‘Jacques Derrida (1930-2004)’, Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, viewed 15 June 2015, <http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/derrida/>.
Minkkinen, P 2007, ‘Ressentiment as Suffering: On Transitional Justice and the Impossibility of Forgiveness’, Law and Literature, vol 19, no 3, pp 513-32.
Norlock, K and Rumsey, J 2009, ‘The Limits of Forgiveness’, Hypatia, vol 24, no 1, pp 100-22.
Wiesenthal, S 1998, The Sunflower: On the Possibility and Limits of Forgiveness, Shocken Books, New York.
Wyschogrod, E 2006, ‘Repenteance and Forgiveness: The Undoing of Time’, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, vol 60, no 3, pp 157-68.